SCU’s Anomalous Aerospace Phenomena Conference (AAPC) 2023 – Day 1

Every podcast, tweet, article … every everything UFO or UAP has, of course, been agog with the Grusch bomb since that fateful day last month. One is left wondering: Will this be one of those “do you remember where you were when Kennedy was shot” moments? (The reference is particularly unsettling, of course, since the recent Schumer legislation, in an act of perhaps unwilful entwinement of real-life intrigue with the sensationalist fluff of conspiracist fantasy-mongering, bases itself on that surrounding efforts to declassify and release documents related to the Kennedy Assassination.) The fallout is left hanging around like a White Noise-style miasma following – in this case – the hapless among us who wish to move on to the more fundamental question of evidence. It is not just a fundamental question, without an examination of which we make no progress in the empirical, factual study of UAP qua object of science (a fraught question, to be sure, and one worthy of careful epistemic diagnostics); it is also a rather basic – no elementary – question.

I will repeat myself: Since no independently verifiable material evidence has been supplied to the general public, which can possibly form the basis for a sound, reasonably informed judgment regarding the factual status of Grusch’s allegations, or which can provide the foundations for an independent assessment as to whether those with supposed “first-hand” knowledge (allegedly of crashed craft, anomalous material fragments, or nonhuman “biologics” associated with any of this) have come to their own beliefs on a sound basis in fact (just what exactly is it these unnamed persons with special access have seen, or think they have seen, and are their claims reasonably secure?) … without any of this, we on the outside of special government access must remain in epistemic limbo. The only reasonable position to maintain here is – let’s see the evidence to substantiate the claims.

I am a bit less inclined than my interlocutor Bryan Sentes is to slide into the skepticism of critical contextualization, which attempts to reduce the current Grusch affair to yet another iteration of some ongoing reproduction of the mythological UFO – “the myth of things seen in the sky” (which by now has become a well-engrained trope on this more skeptical side of the fence). The conversational implication is that the Grusch allegations are dubious because they are more myth than not. I am not inclined towards this position (but one of decided agnosticism) because I distinguish between the mythological UFO and the thing itself, the latter of which stands as an unknown real entering into the sphere of the known (as all “real” phenomena do … and this is the heart of science: even fire was once an unknown). As I have said before, we do not know what to say about these allegations (aside from more speculation both skeptical and believing) just because we do not have access to the relevant evidence. But someone does: namely, the various inspectors general now involved, and who have been involved since at least 2021, as I previously pointed out. (And now apparently there is the first (classified) report of what we should expect will be a number of reports (classified and not) containing the results of their investigations, as I hoped in my previous post on this ongoing affair.)

The mythological UFO (which surely there is) acts as a kind of cypher or epistemic black box into which humanity can dump its fantasies (it even brings them into being), to have them reprocessed and reflected back to us, yielding insights more about the human than about the unknown that is the object-cause of these mythical (and in some cases mystical) productions. (This picture of course is complicated by the phenomenon of the hoax … but let’s not forget that the hoax itself attempts, in its lying playfulness, to reproduce something unknown that inspires the hoax itself, and hence the hoax effectively ends up reaffirming the very reality of the unknown object-cause which it pretends to create.)

The mythological, as with all human productions of meaning, complicates the being of those phenomena that act as objects-cause of the mythical productions. I claim that science was precisely that moment that intersected this mythological world, and countered with a real that acted against the myths while not entirely refuting them. Thus religion in my view is an attempt to domesticate some uncanniness, some unknown phenomenon or phenomena the human being actually encounters (even if only something emergent from the depths of the human psyche—but what is the psyche?); as science determines there to be a “natural” phenomenon operating here, the spell of the myth is broken, and religion is forced to expand or abstract from its specific and systematic attempt to domesticate that uncanniness – its theologies or metaphysics is challenged. Religion changes, perhaps adapting to the new depths provided by the sciences. It is conflictual, to be sure. But on the side of science, it too must operate with a kind of mythical layer to its own discoveries and determinations. Science is not free of either ideology or “myth”.

Here I claim that the myths with which science operates are those that are determined by the implicit metaphysics with which a community of scientists operates, especially when offering its treasure: a scientific explanation of something. In its reductionist tendencies, which posit material mechanisms as the basis for its phenomena, science becomes mythological and ideological. This, too, must be neutralized by a counteracting discourse – and I’ve suggested that this is provided by the standpoint of empiricism, which seeks a metaphysically neutral stance regarding that metaphysical dichotomy, for example, between the material v. the spiritual or mental. So, equally, science, in its own attempts to domesticate the unknown, produces its own myths. It, too, is an ideological factory as it wrestles with that real which resists complete or final conceptual, intellectual determination.

The fundamental problem with the UFO phenomenon is simply that we are confronted with a real unknown, once the procedure of finding an explanation within the existing boundaries of the sciences is exhausted. And that’s the rub: there is no general agreement that this point – the point where we’ve exhausted the set of explanations provided for by existing science – is ever reached. I have pointed out several times that of course this is true, because existing science can always be modified to keep up with anomalies. This is simply an example of the epistemological phenomenon (which becomes a kind of quagmire) philosophers of science have called “underdetermination” (about which we’ve opined before in these pages). And this predicament will never go away. It is simply escaped by theoretical leaps of faith (a begrudgingly-admitted existential dimension of the sciences), corroborated by a structure of empirical data and information that can be coherently and consistently organized by the (new) theory, and if the new theory can also be systematically linked to that which the new theory proposes to replace, then we can perhaps forego a radical revolution (although this needn’t be the case – it’s just a good idea to keep some things we’ve learned in the past as elements or structures, however modified, within the new theory … something like Bohr’s principle of correspondence).

Thus there is and perhaps will be for quite some time the suspicion that any and every UFO sighting, claim, whatever, is only a temporary unknown that will (with certainty) be explained conventionally, mundanely, uncontroversially. Except when it can’t: hence Cmdr. Fravor’s (and his colleagues’) fairly clearly anomalous observations that can’t be convincingly explained away with the desired menu of conventional options. An object he and at least six other “pairs of eyes” (as he puts it) clearly saw approaching his aircraft, only to suddenly fly off to a position over 60 miles away in about a second (which if you’re keeping track, is 216,000 miles per hour). This isn’t much scientific evidence to go on in order to form a solid hypothesis about how the object did what it did; but it is good evidence on which to base a reasonable conjecture – one reasonable in a court of law, for example, or in the science of archaeology – about what it was: a structured object displaying technological capabilities of an unknown nature, under the control of some unknown intelligence. And let’s not get confused about when and what kind of science is relevant and for exactly what claims about these unknowns. This conjecture (about the what it was of the unknown) is simply an attempt to bring this unknown within the realm of the familiar, however problematic it is. (This Bryan Sentes correctly points out in recent Skunkworks posts – to which I respond: yes, ‘technology’ and ‘intelligence’ are surely concepts about which we ought to be very critical … but you have to put the shovel down somewhere, and in any case the complications raised in Sentes’ recent meditation on ‘intelligence’ don’t provide a reason why some forms of intelligence might very well operate with similar kinds of fabricated structures we call technological – just that we have to be careful not to blind ourselves to other possibilities or forms. But then, how would we discover them? … is there an epistemological cul-de-sac somewhere here?)

Once we do this, we can bring to bear our scientific and conceptual resources in an attempt to explain the nature and possibly the origins of this phenomenon and similar unknown phenomena. But in order to get to the point where we can start to offer explanations of these sorts of phenomena, we need good and much better data, of the sort that groups like Galileo Project, UAPx and Hakan Kayal’s IFEX team at Würzburg, are all trying to produce. With this database of good empirical information, we can start to offer a better descriptive taxonomy as a prelude to a better understanding of the nature and potentially the origins of these phenomena – phenomena now categorized very roughly as “UAP” but which will begin to differentiate into more precise subclasses identifiable by means of more exact physical parameters. And then there is the further question of the extent to which some of these anomalous phenomena exhibit even stranger characteristics that truly begin to exit the general framework of scientific thinking. But until we have generally acceptable databases of good empirical information, we’re stuck at the initial stage of phenomenological description – the stage of a young observational science of phenomena for which it is unclear just exactly which science, or what community of sciences, is relevant for a better understanding. Though it’s the physicists, data scientists, engineers and “instrumentalists” who are first in line to study UAP/UFOs, it remains unclear what a science of these phenomena really requires – and perhaps it requires a new science, as I’ve suggested in this blog many times before.

So let’s get back to what I’m actually supposed to be writing about today: the SCU’s AAPC 2023. It began with a talk that picks up on the theme I just introduced – the extent to which UAP harken an upheaval, a revolution, in science. A great question worthy of a deeper, more informed dive than I’ve given it in these pages. And that’s what I was looking forward to hearing about in the alleged “keynote”. But that’s not what we actually got. And so, crankiness began rather quickly for me…

Just to complete the thought with which I began this post by broaching the explosive subject of the Grusch allegations once again: This is all anyone seems to want to talk about in any discussion of UAP, at least right now. Makes sense, I suppose. But the point I was making above is that while some want to retreat to the safety of the all-too-easy contextualization of Grusch’s allegations (and yes, we have been here before, sort of: just read all about it on pp. 85 forward of Thomas Bullard’s absolutely excellent foray into The Myth and Mystery of UFOs, published more than a decade ago now – we just didn’t get these kinds of explosive public hearings in the past), which retreat signals to us that, no, it’s all the same toxic conspiracist fear-mongering conveniently manipulated to good effect as the U.S. enters its second Cold War with Russia/China, this retreat to contextual reduction distracts from the core issue: that there really are UFO cases that resist explanation in ways that really do force the issue of the recalcitrance of an anomaly.

We can’t be misled by some wild allegations by some (seemingly) credible individuals – for which independently verifiable evidence isn’t immediately forthcoming – to think that all UFO claims are equally aberrant. Indeed, we might want to see the Grusch bomb as yet another chapter of the “myth of things seen in the sky” – and maybe it is – but we can’t let the mythological proportions of “the UFO phenomenon”, which largely reflects how we human beings have sought to make meaning of these (real!) “things seen in the sky”, distract us from the more fundamental problem of the reality of these phenomena as disclosed in the few cases like the one Cmdr. Fravor recounts to us, and which is by now well known. The literature on UFOs is replete with such cases. And such literature – correctly described by Watters et al. (2023) as “grey” – must be seen in proper perspective: as indications of a kind of phenomenon (a class of variegated phenomena presenting clear enough physical parameters, amenable to rigorous empirical observations – hence the development and deployment of observational equipment, as detailed in the SCU conference, as well as in the Limina conference I organized back in February) … indications of a class of phenomena that ought to be studied carefully by some subset of our existing sciences. And studied in such a way that we’re looking for what appear to be anomalies.

We are on the hunt for anomalies, meaning that we have to exercise perhaps extra caution that, on the one hand, we’re not finding what we want to find but that, on the other hand, we’re not excluding what we don’t want to find, or aren’t supposed to find, either. In other words, we’ve got to operate in a decidedly liminal space where what is known doesn’t a priori blind us to the possibility that the unknown (the anomalous) might require something new from us, conceptually, theoretically, philosophically. We have to open up to at least four (interrelated) possibilities, all of which, unfortunately (but necessarily) are already always overdetermined by history, by myth, by fiction – by a whole realm of existing human meaning-making: new biology; new intelligence; new technology; new physical principles. Fravor’s “tic-tac” (which, to repeat, was seen by multiple other witnesses) speaks to at least three of these four. But we’re hard-pressed to say anything more specific since we have only witness testimony, some suggestions of radar data (or other “hard” evidence), and little to no other physical evidence on which to hang specific hypotheses regarding the how, the who or the what-exactly (the specific kind of technology he saw – employing the term ‘technology’ here as a placeholder which, indeed, might have to be revisited in a more critical-philosophical register later on). Fravor’s experiences, and those of other witnesses like him, constitutes what we might call the suggestive directional basis for a scientific follow-up – the “grey” literature – that acts, as in medical science, as an indication as to where, how and with what suite of instrumentation to look for these kinds of phenomena. What perhaps is not entirely clear in these discussions is that we start out in scientific forensics, searching backwards from the (perhaps scant) evidence at/for the scene of a crime, to the source – the perpetrator of the crime itself. But in this case, the evidence for the crime, as it were, is itself suggestive (not “proof”) of means and mechanisms which our physics and engineering doesn’t fully understand. That adds a level of complexity to the forensics not typically encountered in this kind of investigation. But this complexity is why the amateur “investigator” – which has been the typical person attached to looking into these phenomena, with wildly varying training and expertise, if at all – isn’t where the empirical study of these phenomena can end. It’s where it begins, only to at some point be turned over to those more skilled in the rigors of strict, scientific observation, data collection and analysis. This is the point at which we transition from mere forensic investigation to scientific research proper (a distinction emphasized to me by the architect of GEIPAN’s own system of UAP case resolution assessment: Michaël Vaillant). Since this proper scientific research program for UAP hasn’t ever existed in any meaningful sense – quite because of the stigma attached to the subject, as we all know – no categorical statements regarding the nature, origins, intentions, physics (or “strangeness”) of any of these phenomena can really be justified beyond the reasonable conjectures we can make based on good UFO cases (a statement, I grant, which requires lots of explanatory follow-up).

Back to the SCU’s AAPC Keynote: former Rear Admiral Tim Gallaudet’s “The New Scientific Revolution”. It was a really poor talk from an academic standpoint, or even from just a basic this-is-supposed-to-be-a-talk-focused-on-the-title kind of a standpoint. I mean, it was a somewhat disjoined and uninformative mélange of well-known UAP cases (like the Nimitz case), sprinkled with interesting suggestions about undersea cases, that just aimed to restate the obvious: there are relatively incredible phenomena being reported by relatively credible individuals (to use the vernacular first articulated by a military official in the early days of uforia in the U.S.). Gallaudet, a member of SCU and board member on Ryan Graves’ new safety-of-flight/UAP-destigmatization initiative, is a retired rear admiral for the U.S. Navy – no slouch as they say – who, besides the other items listed among of imposing credentials, was also a top administrator for NOAA. So, the ocean is his expertise: he has a Ph.D. in oceanography, and so we can say that the retired rear admiral is a scientist as well. But I’m not sure if his research on ocean science alone quite gave him the tools to discuss a potential scientific revolution. Did it provide even anything robust in terms of a reflection on the history of science, the concept of ‘revolution’ in science? Anything beyond what a well-educated person might observe? Didn’t seem so. And it didn’t seem that Gallaudet was interested in doing any serious research on the topic, or at least seeking to inform himself of any existing literature – which is vast and perhaps therefore imposing to the uninitiated – which could have been the basis for some kind of reasoned expansion on the stated theme of the talk. What was really annoying was that the title seemed to be purely cosmetic, almost like click-bate. In a conference that is supposed to be organized by the leading scientific group devoted to the study of UAP, this kind of a talk is totally unacceptable, no matter what the credentials of the speaker are. Indeed, the talk is really an embarrassment to anyone who knows anything about that literature on the history and philosophy of science: lots has been written on the subject, and the least one is intellectually responsible to do is to inform oneself before attempting to position UAP (or the scientific research that’s being attempted on the subject) within this context. Yes, I was grumpy.

More interesting than the admiral’s talk was the ensuing Q&A period, which he seemed eager to get to, and which might explain the hasty quality that his talk displayed: little substance, but lots of fast-moving slides that seemed aimed to get as quickly to the end as possible. And here, as with even the talk itself, we dwelled mostly on the Grusch allegations and all of the government miliary, intelligence and security apparatus surrounding it (a discussion suitably decorated with sometimes oblique, flowery jargon). [At this point, I veered into a long tangent on the Grusch affair—again!, but decided for your, the reader’s mental health, to segregate it safely in an entirely separate post here.]

Occasionally, the focus in Gallaudet’s talk and subsequent Q&A shifted to the other two witnesses called to testify at this bombshell public congressional oversight hearing: Lt. Graves (who gave the keynote at last year’s AAPC) and (ret.) Cmdr. Fravor (who has yet to appear at an SCU event – maybe he’s been invited to other UFO/UAP conferences?). That the testimony of either Graves or Fravor at times only seemed like the second-fiddle is curious, and maybe it’s worth dwelling on this for a moment. If only symbolically, the set up we faced during the hearing was interesting, telling even. Grusch is the central witness, because of the gravity of his claims; on either side are Graves, whose testimony involves recounting what many pilots under his command have had to deal with – near-misses with bizarre UAP, and Fravor, whose testimony recounts what he himself witnessed, along with several of his squadron crew: the now-famous “tic-tac” zig-zagging around a roiling ocean, noticing his approach, and then darting off (at about 210,000mph) to Fravor’s classified rendezvous point. What Graves and Fravor provide for the Grusch testimony is context: yes, the UAP we saw were real objects; they moved in ways not readily explainable; their flight capabilities appeared to far exceed that of any known human tech; ergo, either some gov’t has tech far in advance of U.S. assets, or some UAP are nonhuman tech. And so if some UAP are advanced nonhuman tech (of the sort witnessed by Fravor, or reported on by Graves from his subordinates’ testimony), then the testimony of Grusch is not entirely wildly unbelievable; maybe some of these objects have crashed and have been recovered. At least, this seems to be the (surface-level) symbolic implication of the hearing’s witness positioning…

If that’s so, and the very order of the witnesses called to offer their testimony was a rather deliberate mise en scène, then we have to wonder: How much of the hearing was orchestrated (don’t want to say staged exactly), with the characters positioned quite deliberately, for effect? It doesn’t help when the vociferous and seemingly ubiquitous Jeremy Corbell talks as if the hearing was his baby (for him the admissions are in the interests of “full disclosure”), feeding into the belief that the hearing was far from an impartial, truth-seeking inquest, but a bit of political theater at the expense of the true-believer crowd…

But we digress (again I had to resist including an even longer tangent for the sake of the reader’s sanity). Aside from insights into the inner working of the intelligence community, and other parts of the DOD (to the extent, of course, that Gallaudet could even comment on anything here, since he himself has certain security clearances that bind any of his assertions), nothing much new was learned. I mean, we started out at the beginning of this talk in the zeroth setting of rational epistemic indecision (to repeat: since the material basis for Grusch’s allegations relates to entirely classified disclosure-discussions, documents, etc., none of that material is accessible by the scholarly community at large for independent assessment regarding the veracity or cogency of the claims, documents, photos or anything else to which Grusch alleges to have been privy). And by the end of the talk, we remained at that same zeroth level. Neither Gallaudet’s discussion, nor the breathlessness of the n-th tweet, nor the sum over all podcasts, self-appointed commentators, news follow-ups, op-eds, letters-to-the-editor, interviews with the journalists on the beat, or rebuttals from Pentagon officials … none of this really changes our – i.e., the general public’s – rational epistemology regarding Grusch and his allegations. But that’s probably not why Gallaudet was invited, anyway, since SCU started to plan for their conference a few months ago – even before the early June news bomb from Kean & Blumenthal that broke the story for The Debrief. Still, I wonder why the rear admiral was assigned the dignified slot as keynote, and then why he didn’t supply the SCU’s conference-goers with a robust keynote talk worthy of the attention of serious-minded UAP researchers. For all the heft that a figure such as Gallaudet brings to the affair, it was belied by his actual intellectual performance. It’s a reflection of the very deeply inchoate state of affairs in anything like an academic field called “UAP Studies”. That field doesn’t actually exist as yet, and we struggle to bring it into being. Accordingly, I suppose you’re going to find this kind of content inconsistency. But we press on.

And now for something completely different, I thought as Mr. Rojas—many now know him as part of EnigmaLabs—introduced the next speaker: the young Ph.D. student (soon to be graduate) Inbar Picu, living and studying in Israel. I got to know Inbar personally for a few days while at the excellent workshop I was invited to attend by its organizer, Prof. Alex Wendt (of Ohio State). She’s exactly the kind of student you want to see entering this nascent field (if we can call “UAP Studies” that—though her approach, like many of us thinking about UAP and related matters, is grounded in an existing research tradition, a traditional discipline as it were: in her case it’s International Relations, which is Prof. Wendt’s area of expertise and where he’s a widely respected and well known thinker). Inbar is energetic, consumed by her question, diligent, careful, attentive, thoughtful, respectful of others’ views, open, curious and (I would say) indefatigable (I don’t often use that word). He talk was entitled “What Is There To Talk About? The Framing and Securitization of UFOs in the US New Media Under the UFO Taboo”.

The process of “securitization” is a well-studied phenomenon in International Relations (it may be central to that discipline). As the definition informs, “securitization” is a complex strategic process, internal to a nation state, whereby it seeks to convert some subject, of initially general political concern, into an issue of “security”—national security, of course. This process of transforming some subject into a security matter allows the state to bring to bear its national security and defense apparatus, creating policy, infrastructure, strategic planning, etc. in an effort to mitigate the potential threats that may derive from or arise out of whatever is the significant content of the subject it seeks to securitize. In the case of UFOs, of course, the situation is curious, since by its nature we’re dealing with a disputed reality—or rather, a complicated one that mixes mistake, misperception, hoax, with something there that might really be of national security concern (witness the recent RAND report, which can in effect be read as a strategic recommendation for the government in its attempt to securitize the UAP). What Inbar is very much focused upon—quite significantly, conceptually and philosophically in my view, though I’m no expert—is the imbalance in the scholarship surrounding this process of securitization. The focus in the scholarly literature, she contends, is on when securitization is successful; very little concerns when it fails. Thus the implication (if I might opine here) is that we have a very imbalanced understanding of the process itself—indeed, if we don’t know what failure is, we won’t be able to perceive the structural or even strategic limitations of an attempt to securitize something. This has, I think, important practical implications, if only for policymakers and those involved in the material processes of securitization, for, not knowing the nature of securitization failures, we don’t know what exactly to recommend on possible subjects of (successful) securitization—we don’t know because we don’t clearly know why something failed to be securitized. If all we know are successes, then we’re effectively always guessing, and muddling through with no clear direction—stuck in: maybe, let’s try this, let’s try that. So this, then, this gets to an even more fundamental question: what are the conditions under which something can be successfully securitized? All we know from the literature are those cases where it succeeds, not when or where it’s failed (it’s not studied), so, in a sense, we don’t really know what securitization is—just when it has worked. In other words: we have “techne” but no “episteme” (to use the ancient Greek epistemological distinction some readers might be familiar with), know-how without knowledge per se.

In any case, maybe I’m wrong here and this really doesn’t amount to a worry, or even to the most important worry, but this was a concern which prefaced Inbar’s talk. In order to examine the process of securitization of the UFO (or UAP, rather), which she argues began in earnest with the ODNI report in 2021, she examines the structure of the discourse surrounding UAP, as it appears especially in the news media, to get clues about how exactly the process is in play for this subject. It is, as she describes it, a “discourse analysis”. I wonder, however, if a discourse analysis of news media is the right focus—but for all I know that’s how one begins to study securitization, or it’s an approach unique to Inbar herself. Shouldn’t one attempt an analysis that balances discourse in media—which is external to the defense and security apparatus that enacts securitization—with discourse internal to those agencies which are directly involved in structuring the securitization? I also wonder if the periodization she’s adopted for when securitization begins is well-motivated: surely securitization has been attempted (perhaps abortively) ever since the UFO phenomenon broke out during and after the Second World War. If anything, what we see with UFOs (now UAP) is periodic securitization: starting and stopping of the process. Perhaps this adds another dimension of uniqueness and complexity to the securitization of the UFO/UAP (indeed: perhaps the shift in name is itself structurally significant for securitization, in that it indicates important shifts in attention, perspective and perception). Inbar also concerns her study with the aspect of taboo that functions within the discourse around UFOs/UAP—and here she cites the seminal Wendt paper, who, as it turns out, is one of her Ph.D. thesis advisors. It was an excellent, and academically substantial talk, I thought. Not like the keynote.

Following Inbar’s talk was one by Prof. Richard Griffiths, a rather distinguished professor of (observational) astronomy and physics, emeritus at Carnegie Mellon, now living and teaching (I believe) in Hawaii (not a bad place to which to retire—though the recent catastrophic fires in Maui are a wake-up call). I had the occasion to hear his talk (or something close to it) when I attended the AAAF seminar (“Optical Observables of UAP”) in France back at the beginning of June this year, so I elected to skip this talk and turn my attention to friends and family here in Cairo. (The talk was an exposition of Griffith’s UAP case study, which he entitled “A Very Large UAP crosses the North Pacific: Observed by Five Pilots, with two Photos and a Video”. Curiously, the talk is no longer on-demand like most of the others. I suspect this is because, as it has come to light, the case is most likely best explained by a satellite deployment—probably Starlink. As the work of people like Mick West rightly demonstrates, as we investigate UAP cases we must simultaneously educate ourselves on the phenomenology of those technological phenomena which are new in our skies but unfamiliar; the “debunkers” do very crucial work, and must always be respectfully and attentively studied.)

Following the Griffiths presentation, was a talk by one of the Galileo Project’s student researchers: Abigail White, who’s gained some notoriety through the Ryan Graves (uneven in my view) “Merged” podcast. While her story is a sensitive recounting of her “journey”, I found the talk to be very much inappropriate for a conference on something like the scientific study of UAP. I mean, the talk had no real content to offer the community, besides a self-portrait of a young researcher just trying to figure out where she wants to go next in her career. What was really odd about the whole thing was that, almost as an afterthought, she admits she won’t really be pursuing UAP in her upcoming Ph.D. research studies! Or at least that’s what I thought I heard. So what’s the lesson from this self-portraiture? In what content relevant to the conference there was in the talk, it was mostly a general survey of some of the architecture of the GP’s multimodal observational “suites”, which range from modestly-priced smaller apparatuses to much larger, and pricier, stationary systems. But mostly this part of the presentation was meant to explain where she worked on the project and what instrumentation she was particularly concerned to work with. I mean, it’s interesting and all, but I thought it wasn’t appropriate to go personal journey on those in attendance. Maybe it’s a generational thing…

Next—and we detect a clear theme here—was another student (Robin Schaub), offering a much more substantial presentation on a reporting and analysis system being developed and deployed at his university: Würzburg, the homebase of Prof. Dr. Hakan Kayal (whom Schaub’s working with), who is one of the most important, serious, robustly academic scientists involved in the contemporary effort to study UAP scientifically (in Germany, no less—a country that suffers even more from the debilitating taboo that, as we know, has beleaguered attempts to study UAP seriously). The system Schaub detailed is a project of a UAP-focused group at Würzburg: “IFEX”. Auf Deutsch, the name fully spelled out is: Interdisziplinäres Forschungszentrum für Extraterrestrik, or in their preferred English vernacular: Interdisciplinary Research Center for Extraterrestrial Studies. (One might pause to complain about the “extraterrestrial studies” here, but we have to remember that part of their focus, being lodged within a space sciences program at the university, is well, extraterrestrial: things outside of and beyond the earth proper. (It’s all spelled out in detail on their website, linked supra.) That, and the association was formed in 2017, just as renewed attention, and scrutiny, emerged for UAP.)

What was curious about Schaub’s presentation was that he positioned it in relation to an existing system employed in France—but which he only mentioned in passing, revealing a lack of understanding of what exactly “this system” is. I presume Schaub was gesturing towards the GEIPAN system. If that’s so, then it’s unsurprising he doesn’t know much about it, because GEIPAN hasn’t exactly gone out of its way to detail their system, or provide much insight for non-French speakers (which, unfortunately, is most of the world; English is very much the lingua franca today—yes, with all due irony and respect to Français, which indeed had that status, sort of, some centuries ago, when the cultural imperialism of empire wasn’t so totalizing). It’s a tragedy for current UAP research, but it’s part of a general phenomenon I’ve noticed (perhaps explained by the persistence of the taboo Pincu worried about in her talk): the lack of UAP-related research contained in searchable databases scholars regularly access. Anyone, like Schaub, just starting out in this area has a monumentally difficult challenging (needlessly so) in finding, studying, and then incorporating the results of past work immediately relevant to their own. It is an elementary but importantly preliminary exercise to engage in a thorough literature review before one begins to develop their own work in a given discipline or field. For UAP, not only is there really no field as such—but the work is (therefore) scattered amongst publications in already-legitimate fields or disciplines, or embedded in what Prof. Watters of the Galileo Project has recently called the “gray literature” of uneven quality, sometimes questionable integrity, and therefore of limited or uncertain scholarly usability (certainly not something that can be uncritically cited as authoritative—an enduring and perhaps under-addressed methodological quandary vexing UAP scholarship going forward).

The GEIPAN system provides two things: on the front-side, there is a place to report your (or a) UAP/UFO sighting/encounter/incident—they ask you to “testify” (but the website is stubbornly resistant to English translation). But on the backside, as I have come to learn, there is a very sophisticated UI for the investigative team (though it could be a single investigator working on a case-of-interest—the COIs). And it’s here that the process really begins, from initial report (uploaded by the witness(s) or manually entered by GEIPAN), follow-up (after a kind of triage system), to the software-system-generated set of hypotheses attempting to offer a possible explanation for the sighting—ranked in a clever way, according to two dimensions: “robustness” and “strangeness”. The suitably analyzed COIs are at some point shunted over to a “college of experts” (sans periwigs one assumes) to take a (presumably well-informed and educated) vote on how to classify the case. And it’s their system of classification that, while of course not perfect, is (or should be) a model of what needs to be happening (attention: AARO … let’s not reinvent the wheel). There are four classes into which a UAP incident case is put: A, B, C, and D. The A’s are nearly proven to be something known; the B’s are those that are shown to be probably something known. The C’s are those cases for which there is lack of reliable data, and so the cases must remain undetermined. Whereas—and here’re the cases of most interest to those of us who want to get down to scientific and scholarly business—the D’s are … and please let’s pay attention to what GEIPAN is saying here … those which, while having sufficiently reliable information and adequate data on which to make a determination, nonetheless fail to be understood as containing a report of a known phenomenon of some kind. The D cases are further subdivided into D1 (“strange”) and D2 (“very strange”). It’s the D’s that are passed on for further investigation—forensic follow-up. They are thus, in effect, cases that are submitted to field investigators for reevaluation. Thus, a D might be converted into A or B (presumably the fact that it’s deemed a D case means C—cases that lack sufficient data—is no longer an applicable label).

What GEIPAN does not do, after looking into the D’s, is research further to see what explanation would work, once the reevaluation process is complete. That’s the point at which a science begins, for these cases are those which would seem to suggest “truly new empirical observations” (to use Hynek’s expression, which I’ve come to like).

Schaub shows us that they’ve got some part of this kind of thing in the works, and partially up-and-running. But what’s importantly different here is that suites of observational equipment will be part of the hypothesis-generation mode of the initial analysis of the UAP case data. This is important, since it will begin to integrate live, empirical data that can be used to create a richer informational tapestry, from which one can derive more secure analytical conclusions. Indeed, in so doing, we begin the process of converting the data from mere UAP report to factual (and verifiable) data on the UAP itself. (Let’s not forget Vallée’s important proviso, which haunts the science of these phenomena: we deal not with the UFO, but with the report of the UFO…) But there was one thing I caught from Schaub’s talk that was potentially worrisome, and that’s the stated desire to “delete the role” or participation of the human subject in the UAP incident. I think he means to mitigate the potential biases introduced in the testimony supplied as part of the data on a UAP incident. One cannot “delete” the human from anything—for then we’d have nothing of meaning or significance on which to work. (This is a characteristic concern of the humanities in dealing with how, methodologically speaking, the scientists propose to go about studying UAP, and why humanists and social scientists have to be involved in some reciprocally significant way. Thus we bring the Society for UAP Studies to bear…)

After a short break, we found two final events: one more talk, related to the work members of SCU itself were conducting (let’s not forget SCU is in essence a think-tank), and a closing “AIAA” panel which provided a series of (shorter) pre-recorded talks derived from the three papers accepted by and presented to the American Institute of Aeronautics and Astronautics.

The talk, “A Descriptive Analysis of the Characterization of Unidentified Aerial Phenomena Cases” involved an exposition of the SCU’s study of UAP shapes—a kind of phenomenology of UAP visual presentations. And by “phenomenology” I don’t mean anything particularly specific—which lack of specificity here might ultimately be a problem for (or weakness of) the study. What’s the underlying theory driving the descriptive method? Phenomenology, at least in philosophy, means something very specific; there are strict methods applied to the examination of the data of first-person conscious human experience. So, one issue here might be that what’s examined is just the (uncritical, maybe phenomenologically naïve) claims, made in reports, about how various UAP appear. So, we might say that it’s not phenomenological in a rigorous philosophical sense (and I guess it needn’t be—at least not initially); it’s a characterization of what people say they see in reports that the authors of the study chose to include. I don’t yet see the paper published at the SCU’s website, so I don’t want to comment further (it’s just a talk, after all), but it will be interesting to see if there is a critically examined and explicit methodological underpinning (which perhaps bears some relation to an accepted methodology in use elsewhere in science or scholarship) to their shape characterization study. If we want to do serious work, we can’t just stay within the parameters of UAP discourse, or of classical ufology; we must (as with some of the other work SCU has produced) try to ground the study in something well-understood elsewhere in existing (and, ideally, uncontested) scholarship. This ought to be a meta-theoretic methodological criterion guiding UAP Studies…

Finally, the panel. The three, very high-quality, substantial (and technical) talks here were:

Peter Reali’s “System Study of Constraints for the Creation of UAP Electromagnetic Signature Optimal Detection Systems.”

Ralph Howard’s “FAA Unmanned Aircraft Systems (UAS) Sighting Reports: A Preliminary Survey.”

Tim Oliver’s physics-heavy “Aerodynamic Interactions and Turbulence Mitigation by Unidentified Aerospace-undersea Phenomena.”

Only a few scattered comments are in order, as I’ve doubtlessly already taxed the reader’s patience (and need for sleep).

What Mr. Reali talked about was work done on examining just what it would take, across the board, to really get optimal detection rates for UAP, given what we know about their frequencies of occurrence as a function of geographic location. Just how much geography does one have to cover, to get optimal (EM/optical) detection? That’s a hard question to answer in detail, though it’s not hard to set up the problem itself, as Peter does very naturally, and with obvious competence. The work is practically relevant—he’s an engineer, after all, so practicals (like, so how much are we talking?) have to matter at some point. The talk breaks it down: there are so many geographic regions that need to be covered, and with a certain swath of aerospace able to be scanned, relative to the instrument-specific specs (that are a necessary factor to consider here), this determines the total number (and type) of systems needed. And you can put a price tag on that (it’s in the millions for each subsector—but not insanely unreachable budgetary goals, esp. considering the total U.S. national defense budget … lol’s all ‘round: we can do this if we’re serious about it).

I was sadly distracted by house-matters during Ralph’s talk, but I did manage to catch the bulk of Tim Oliver’s (well, ok, I’ll admit to being enthused about any physics talks related to UAP). What we got here was a substantial study of one of the hallmark phenomenological features of many UAP reports (or at least, those of a certain type): the observed and sometimes radar-recorded rapid acceleration to extreme (hypersonic) velocity of apparently structured objects but with no discernible sonic-boom or other—expected—thermal signatures. Is it possible, the talk asks in effect, to model this with known physics? Apparently, it is: you can mitigate the propagation of the shock wave or other thermal energy through the generation of a surrounding force field (of some kind) which acts to counter these effects (basically, of a rigid object passing through a fluid). Or so proposed the perhaps obscure but significant UFO researcher Paul Hill (NASA scientist no less) in a little-read tome entitled Unconventional Flying Objects: A Scientific Analysis (1995). And this was Oliver’s theoretic starting point (practicing classic scholarship in the process: starting off where others have left off).

The approach adopted by Oliver, following Hill, uses computational fluid dynamics (CFD) to create the basic model for how the hypothetical field of force behaves with respect to the surrounding fluid (which is what the media, through which the UAP would travel, are conceived to be—at least for the purposes of this analysis) in order the get the right effects to work out that would be needed to suppress or nullify the stuff we dont but should observe (sonic-booms, etc.). But what is (or would be) the nature of this hypothetical force field? In an analytical tactic that goes all the way back to Newton himself (who similarly just looked for the mathematical/physical form the force we now call gravity must take, which acts in this case universally on all material bodies), Oliver in effect splits this problem into two, independently tractable ones. First find the form that this field-of-force must take in order to achieve the desired effects (mitigating sonic-booms, etc.); then ask what physical mechanism or process could create such a field with the required properties. As far as I can tell, Oliver has completed the first part of the problem, and the second one still remains an open question (though I am no expert, so my claims here are tentative).

So then, first, following Hill, we can simply ask: what form should a counteracting force field  take (what must its mathematical/physical properties be), in order to cancel (or otherwise nullify) the resulting shock-waves (and other thermal effects due to frictional forces acting on a rapidly moving rigid body through a fluidic medium)? In the introduction to his paper submitted to AAAS, and presented to them (a paper not yet peer-reviewed, but just released on the SCU website), Oliver writes that (and we quote him at length):

“Hill proposed that fast-moving objects can manipulate the surrounding flow field by imposing a force field. This method, which draws on potential flow theory, involves equating the force field potential to the kinetic energy associated with the flow. The engineered force field can theoretically counteract the kinetic energy of the flow, resulting in a constant density, constant pressure flow without energy losses. When correctly formulated and employed, the force field should produce speed-independent flow patterns that apply to both compressible and incompressible fluid flows.

So, once the details of this flow structure are worked out (and that constitutes the bulk of Olivers analysis, at least in the paper), we can then move on to part two of the problem, which involves a question about what the exact nature of the force field itself could be, as in: what could the physics of this field be? What know what form that force field must take, and the properties it must exhibit, but is there anything physical that can satisfy these theoretical demands? Presumably, those finer details (like the particular equations that would describe the behavior of the force field, as Hill requires there to be, which surrounds a UAP and is supposed to enable its evidently smooth, shock-free travel) could be derived from the principles of magnetohydrodynamicsMHD, as they call it in the biz, seems to be an increasingly popular alternative conception to how exactly the UAP can move so fast. That is, MHD is a popular alternative to even more speculative (and conceptually problematic) accounts of UAP kinematics using what they call metric engineering but which you probably know as warp drive (yes, the Star Trek thing). Maybe we can exploit this same hypothetical MHD propulsion mechanism to also explain the absence of sonic booms? (At least, this is the question I would pose.) In other words, the question here is: could a suitably engineered (magnetohydrodynamic) plasma do the trick? If so, then we might be able to come up with a unifying explanatory model of UAP kinematics, since if the plasma is also related to the propulsion (an MHD drive of some kind), then we have an idea even of the architecture of the technology that has been engineered (presumably by whatever intelligence(s) is(are) responsible for these evidently structured objects) for trans-medium (and especially atmospheric) travel at extreme velocity (greater than Mach 5; for example, the tic-tac Fravor describes appeared to move at over 200,000mph and that works out to be, in air, a cool Mach 260 or so. I mean, is that even hypersonic anymore?).

In my personal view (which is not necessarily endorsed by Oliver or part of his papers analysis), according to this CFD + MHD model you’d basically be dealing with the interaction between two fluids manifesting different physical properties (electromagnetically active plasma and air, for sky-bound UAP, or water, for submerged ones), so the key is in understanding exactly how the (proposed) MHD plasmoid surrounding a (hypothetical) UAP interacts with the rest of the medium-of-travel in the UAP’s immediate physical environment. (I suppose the creation of the plasma would at some point entail, at least along the surface where the plasma interacts with atmosphere, ionization, and that might be useful in mitigating the thermal effects, sonic-booms etc.)

In any case, I dont want to get ahead of what Oliver has very carefully worked out (especially since I’m not a physicist). In his conclusion, he writes (and again we quote his recently-released paper at length):

“The[ese] research findings highlight the significant stabilizing effect that an applied force field can have on flow field pressure and flow patterns, particularly in compressible cases. This suggests the potential to utilize an engineered force field to neutralize any pressure differences that may arise within the flow field when objects move rapidly through compressible and incompressible media. The study demonstrated that the force field strength would need to be proportional to the square of velocity to achieve the desired effect, and the form of the resultant pressure field is largely speed-independent.

“To implement this approach, the force field strength could be adjusted according to the craft's velocity, allowing it to be used across a range of speeds. However, challenges may arise at higher speeds due to increased misbalanced forces. Rapid maneuverability would necessitate rapid changes of field strength, and radial movements of the object would necessitate changes in field form. Furthermore, when passing through atmospheric pressure disturbances, continuous monitoring and adjustments to the force field's strength and shape may be necessary.

“Despite these concerns, the use of an engineered force field, whilst speculative, could offer a potential explanation for the lack of interference of fast-moving objects in compressible and incompressible media, potentially preventing the formation of shock waves and aerodynamic heating for objects traveling at extreme speeds in the atmosphere.”

With this, Day One of the 2023 AAPC closed. I went to sleep that evening very happy in the end, after having gotten very cranky with the keynote and with some talks that were, in my view, inappropriate or otherwise insubstantial additions to an evidently professional and scientific conference. I was therefore enthused about and very much looking forward to Day Two.

Which Ill get to in my next post...

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Rising Sun In The UFO Firmament: Reflections on the Sol Foundation’s Inaugural Symposium. Part One of Two.

Of SCIF’s, OIGs and IGs: More on the Grusch Affair

Possible & Impossible: On the Second Edition of Archives of the Impossible. Part One.