Of workshops and colloquia: a foray into ufological circles and discussions
Before I get to the past, let’s deal with the future.
While attempting to fulfil my duties as president and acting
director of the Society for UAP Studies, and lecturer in philosophy, I
have been trying to work out some of my ideas on matters related to the study
of UAP—which of course inevitably brings
one to the doorstep, if not the very interior of, the “ETH”. And with that one
must inevitably wonder about the nature of the “ET” in the H. But—as you have
come to expect, perhaps, from me as a philosophically-inclined writer on
ufological matters—one must wonder even more fundamentally, as my friend Bryan
Sentes has often stressed, about the very concept of “intelligence” and what is
presupposed by it. Having been positively (and sometimes negatively—but in a
good way!) influenced by Bryan’s subtle questioning and interrogation of the
issue, I am increasingly more inclined to think that while it might be somewhat
obvious (for some cases, both historical and future) that there is an
intelligence behind some (and by no means all) UAP, because of the radical
empirical distance between human and nonhuman, non-terrestrial being,
coming to know what that intelligence is, and the extent to which the
notion of ‘technology’ is suitable for such being, is going to be a much harder
question to resolve. And I think it will be complicated by the fact that, most
likely, there will be a great range of kinds of intelligence in play, each
perhaps with a characteristic relationship to the tools they fashion and use.
Some perhaps will seek to ambiguate the dichotomy—pronounced for homo faber—between
creator-user and tool used. What SETI expects, for example, is to detect
technologically-induced atmospheric peculiarities in the distant worlds whose
spectra we are just now being able to study in detail (thanks of course to new
and more powerful observation technologies); and with even more powerful
technologies of observation, to perhaps see the megastructures and other
shiny add-ons that a technology-using extraterrestrial civilization would
construct atop their world. But as water worlds might be more common, this
could be complicated by beings who prefer an oceanic and submarine lifestyle.
But the presupposition here is that there will be differences in these
distant world’s observable, physical characteristics that will point to
technology and hence to the operation of some extraterrestrial intelligence.
Indeed, the historical irony here is that science has fallen back on the
favorite “proof” of theologically-inclined intellectuals (and “natural
philosophers”) of the 17th and 18th centuries: the
“Design Argument”. William Paley, of course, gives us its classical form (which
we quote at length):
In crossing a heath, suppose I
pitched my foot against a stone, and were asked how the stone came to be there;
I might possibly answer, that, for anything I knew to the contrary, it had lain
there forever: nor would it perhaps be very easy to show the absurdity of this
answer. But suppose I had found a watch upon the ground, and it should be
inquired how the watch happened to be in that place; I should hardly think of
the answer I had before given, that for anything I knew, the watch might have
always been there. ... There must have existed, at some time, and at some
place or other, an artificer or artificers, who formed [the watch] for the
purpose which we find it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction,
and designed its use. ... Every indication of contrivance, every
manifestation of design, which existed in the watch, exists in the works of
nature; with the difference, on the side of nature, of being greater or more,
and that in a degree which exceeds all computation.
From which we are supposed to derive the conclusion that
there must be a grand Designer, God…
SETI, of course, seeks to establish not that there is God, but
that, if we happen upon the equivalent of a watch on some distant world, then
“there must have existed, at some time, and at some place or other, an
artificer or artificers, who formed” it “for the purpose which we find it
actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use”.
The presupposition here being that its “contrivance” and “design” is
manifest—that is, plainly and unambiguously given. Surely this is only
the case because our recognition—in Paley’s famous little thought-experiment—is
given by an object of our own familiar design. And equally as surely for Paley, Nature
Herself manifestly exhibits a design which requires there be a Designer. The
modern scientific rejoinder to this logic is a double critique: (i) the
attribution is an anthropomorphic projection and illicit generalization to all
of nature (no caps), who operates (ii) by blind (unintelligent) chance (with a
logic all of its own: the logic of random but constrained and therefore
knowable circumstance: enter evolutionary biology—the Darwinian reply).
Yet, if we focus just on the artifice of the object itself, we might convert
this theological argument into an argument for the (inferential) existence of
ETI on a distant world, thus resurrecting the theological argument and
repurposing it for SETI. But what about the argument that Paley was
anthropomorphizing: projecting a human concept of design onto nature? Well, but
if we don’t attempt the projection onto nature as a whole, and hence use the
concept of design, patterned after something clearly human in origin, illicitly
in that way, then we can (surely?) use it as the basis for recognizing the
designs of another designer like ourselves, right? Well, that would seem
right—except that we’d have to be able to recognize those designs as designs—an
“artifice” distinct from the general pattern of the “natural world” which would
not to us indicate the existence of an intelligence. So, are the necessarily
anthropomorphic concepts of design, artifice etc. harmless in this case? We are
back to the N = 1 problem: we only have one example of “technology” and
(supposedly) nonnatural “artifice” to go on, and that’s the shiny, polluting,
invasive and adjunct apparatus of modern technoscience, which inserts itself
all over the globe in ways that, for us, seem both obvious and (to some)
unfortunate. Yet to a distant observer, perceiving us with a radically distinct
set of presuppositions (that perhaps do not entail a radical distinctness
between tool and user/being, or between being intelligent and being
natural—i.e., a “nature” of nonseparable wholes and parts), it might be that we
are seen, together with our tools, as part of one whole system of (natural)
being. And if those distant, extraterrestrial observers (and maybe they have
stopped by already?) cannot (or will not) separate us from nature as we
separate ourselves from it, then wouldn’t we expect silence from them,
overlooking us for a larger view of the whole? (Notice, this is not the “ant”
hypothesis many like to toy with when it comes to thinking about the possible
nature of an ETI; rather, I am saying that it might just be incompatible
conceptual presuppositions—which has nothing at all to do with a supposed
difference in intelligence—that inhibits contact or communication. They needn’t be “hyper-advanced” for there to
be a communicative mismatch … yet another dubious anthropomorphism I suppose: “advanced” by what measure?)
This gives you some sense of the kind of questions and
problems to which I’ve turned my mind in recent months. I only go on at length
about this because I have submitted (with Bryan) two abstracts to two run-of-the-mill
academic conferences which propose to broach the subject of UAP in relation to
the ETI hypothesis—but in an effort to problematize any future “contact”
scenario. Or at least to interrogate it in a more fundamental philosophical
register. But not only ETI. I have proposed that even the UAP itself, as it
inhabits what I’ve called a “liminal” space (intersecting the known while at
the same time exiting it), presents a more subtle challenge as they, by
their own appearances (and there are important differences among the various
UAP encounters that are rather pertinent here), problematize our conceptual
space of recognition. We see them—but how? We attempt to conceptualize
them—but how? Their empirical distance from us (in more ways than one) suggests
a more fundamental problem: one of quite radical difference, something
that is even anterior to “otherness” or “alterity” (to use the philosophical
lingo). It’s a kind of difference that occasions (I want to argue) a new space
of conceptual possibilities, something outside the coordinates of “natural” v.
“artificial” and so on. Or in any case the UAP are an occasion (at least for
some encounters) for a significant alteration and change in our concepts. But
we have to think ourselves into this new space, thinking with
these phenomena as they challenge those concepts we have ready-at-hand for them.
There is a third conference to which I’ve sent an abstract,
but this one is a conference on (basically) foundational issues in the theory
of probability and probabilistic inference, and I am second or third author
(with some others in the UAP Studies community). And here we are attempting to
interrogate the problem (in Bayesian inference theory) of prior probabilities,
which seems to always militate against truly “new empirical observations” that compel
progress in science: if every potential anomaly is always given a very low
probability against the more likely conventional explanations of it, then
science cannot change—it cannot find a new paradigm formed around and suited
to the specifics of the anomaly itself. Rather, it will always seek to
extend the dominant paradigm (by introducing any number of paradigm-saving
hypotheses). Yet, we know that science has changed; indeed, we accept that
change is part of the very essence of science as such (as a method of discovering
the structure of nature, the dazzle of the real). So, we might ask (following
the so-called “transcendental” method of Kant—whom I have yet to introduce to this
project!): how is scientific change possible, since we know that it does
change? That is: what are the conditions of the possibility of scientific
theory change—even radical theory change (as in the transition from Aristotle
to Galileo-Kepler-Newton)? It has to rest with the acceptance of scientific
anomalies, or at least with the embrace of the (un-theorized) new. But how does this happen? Since it cannot be an exactly rational
procedure internal to a given paradigm, then change must be extrinsic to a
paradigm, and must derive from the inner structure of the phenomena themselves,
which compel the creative postulation of new theory. That is, the anomaly
represents a potentially new framework with respect to which there will
be new meaning to certain key concepts. Thus, the assignment of the
prior probabilities must be contextualized or relativized: either
the prior probability of an extraordinary hypothesis (that there is a genuine
anomaly not strictly explicable by means of existing science) is determined relative
to the existing paradigm—in which case the probability will be very low—or
it is given relative to a new paradigm, which would be the one implied
by the anomaly itself. In this case, we would have to examine the priors relative
to a context of anomalies: if the existing paradigm suffers from several or
many, then this would raise the likelihood that we, indeed, have a genuine
anomaly and have reason to believe that the extraordinary hypothesis is more
likely than not (especially if the anomaly can be linked to other anomalies in
some systematic fashion). At least this is my (so-far only partially-baked)
contribution to the paper. We’ll see…
I will also be traveling, on the 9th of May, to the second iteration of the Archives of the Impossible, which is Prof. Jeffrey Kripal’s initiative at Rice University to collect, house and make available a whole range of documents and other sundry resources related to—and what should the term here be?—the uncanny, the strange … that which doesn’t easily fit in with the conventional. Here I will meet the more “woo” crowd (though I hate that term). For my own part (and not to predetermine myself as dogmatic) I represent something of an alternative view of the alternatives. As I’ve attempted to outline in my blog posts over the course of the previous year (and it’s official: though I have slowed my writing these past several months, Entaus is one year old), I am trying to work out a kind of empiricism of the unconventional.
Yesterday in the shower (where lots of ideas seem to percolate from the depths of my unconscious—water is truly rejuvenating to the soul), I had an insight into what it seems that I am trying to say. Let me try to recover this flash of a thought: In the 17th century, Science came to embrace two traditions—the one speculative and conceptual, disciplined by mathematics and elaborated as metaphysics; the other experimental, almost alchemical in a new sense but disciplined by the mathematical and the metaphysical. This produced something remarkable: as the great philosophical writer on the New Science Sir Francis Bacon would conceptualize it, through the synthesis of these traditions, human beings were given a new power of creation. Heretofore hidden potencies of Nature were expressed and brought to light, removed from the darkness of natural secrecy, and opened to the power of human understanding, control and intervention. The metaphysical and mathematical descriptions of Nature, passed through the alchemy of experimentation, produced new forms under the direct control of the human experimenter. Newton (secret alchemist by night) would then show that we could discharge the metaphysical specifics (those “substances” or “essences” of the old medieval Schools) yet retain the structure of relationships that reliably and consistently produced certain observable results or predictions, which could then form the basis of our understanding of Nature: we might not know what gravity itself, metaphysically speaking, is (Descartes had proposed that it was really a plenum of material “vortices” and so really was a matter of frictional forces pulling on things), but its formal, mathematical structure could be given (as a certain characteristic equation, that expressed the right structural relationships between the relevant phenomena). Fast-forward to the breakthroughs of the late 19th and early 20th centuries: we could now not only reproduce and control phenomena heretofore totally unknown to human beings (the phenomena of radiation and radioactive decay surely were all around us, but imperceptible and uncontrollable), but could bring into being phenomena possible but not so far expressed by nature herself. For example, fission, and of course the atomic bomb, wasn’t a process or technique nature seemed to care to express on her own (aside from the randomness of radioactivity); yet, human beings managed to express it for her (for better or for worse). Fusion, the basic process behind the sun, was the very origin of our own life here on Earth (and the process behind the creation of the atomic elements on which that life relies), is already expressed everywhere in the universe, and is a process we are on the verge of mastering for ourselves: Imitatio Dei. Various quantum processes are underway everywhere—but quantum entanglement is much rarer in nature; yet, we can bring this into being (difficult though it is) and make nature express it. What other processes, like fission, still yet remain entirely hidden within the bosom of nature but which, unlocked by the key of insight, will be made manifest—perhaps for the first time in the history of the universe? Surely the entire range of what we now call “paranormal” might be said to be a kind of hint, a dim suggestion of what is possible on the basis of principles of nature yet unknown to us?
How much of our knowledge is simply a function of our perhaps rather peculiar portion of the universe to which we have, for contingent reasons, a certain kind of access? We’ve been thrown into the world at a certain time and place, and though through our vision and our extended perception (by means of more exotic electromagnetic and gravitational interactions) we see everywhere the things we see here in our immediate experience, how much of what we experience isn’t representative of this vast expanse of the Real? The New Science, if it taught us anything, taught us the humility of patient empirical engagement with nature, which by a painstaking process of experimentation and theorization, slowly but surely reveals what is hidden. Nature is the ultimate horizon outside of which there is nothing. Everything is within nature. Paranormal or not. We have only to go deeper to get the unexpressed (or partially expressed) to be more fully expressed. In this way does the human—or any other being of this kind of transformational intelligence—become a constitutive element of the very being of nature herself: a productive and creative element of the very unfolding of the real of nature. We are an expressive function of nature even as we make nature express what is hidden within her. I don’t know if this is why Kripal calls the human “two”, but surely we must have patience—the patience of the empirical.OK, well, that was much more of an elaboration of the insight
I had than I had intended—and one perhaps diluted because of the prolixity of
its expression. It will have to be tightened and pared down for it to be as succinct
as the original flash had seemed to me. But this is my best first attempt. Let it
stand.
So much for the future. But what about the (immediate) past?
Let’s talk about those three ufologically oriented events I had the pleasure to
attend…
During the week of March 13th, I attended a
workshop organized by Alex Wendt and hosted by the Mershon Center at Ohio State
University. The title of this event was given as “Bringing SETI Home: National
Security and the Politics of UAP”. The idea was to bring in a number of
scholars from a range of disciplines to discuss various national security and
political issues raised by UAP—if we take UAP “seriously” (that is, as
more than misperception, hoax, or instrument error). I’m not quite at liberty
to disclose who exactly was present, since the taboo against the subject is
still strong and a number of the scholars gathered at the event don’t want their
careers jeopardized, but there were many present who are quite serious and well-respected
within their respective disciplines. Indeed, I was impressed by both the range
and the quality. It was only a two-day event, but it was exciting, dynamic and
very intellectually fruitful. Such a profound spirit of collegiality and
helpfulness dominated throughout its two days that it could be said that this
event was unique—even among more mainstream academic workshops (at least that I have
attended over the years). We were gathered in a spirit of collaboration and intellectual
exchange while recognizing the difficulties inherent to the topic—which we
always kept foregrounded as we discussed and debated. My sense was that this is
precisely the kind of thing that’s needed in a field that is so young: if these
were exercises in “UAP Studies”—which I’d argue they most certainly were—then we
went some distance in trying to experiment with methods and discourse that
could be foundational to it. It was a rich and deeply meaningful experience, to
say the very least.
For my own part, I presented a talk (based on a very preliminary paper) on UAP and climate change—perhaps a strange pair. But there were papers from those involved with SETI (exploring the problematic relation between UAP and SETI); from those concerned with the politics of any potential “disclosure”; from those concerned with the ethics of a potential military engagement with UAP; and from those concerned with issues of “securitization” of UAP (and this tended to be the general concern of the workshop as a whole). We have planned to develop our papers and talks into chapters for a volume of essays, possibly titled with the title of the workshop itself. There will be three editors of this potential volume, and we’re looking to attract Oxford University Press. We’re hopeful that they’d be interested. If so, then this could very well be a watershed moment for UAP Studies. Our due date for finished papers is fixed for sometime in the middle of January of next year, so it’ll be a while before the thing sees the light of day. But it’s in the works, and should, when finally released, be a rather interesting read…
On March 16th I arrived home. I had flown into Detroit for Columbus, OH from LA, but now found myself returning to LAX (which is essentially a second home for me now) on March 20th, for one of those late-evening departures out to Europe that seem to be rather common. I booked myself onto the big Airbus 380—quite an experience in modern aviation. It’s a wonder the thing can get airborne. But airborne we were, after almost a minute of acceleration down the runway. Off to England I went for event no. 2: a one-day colloquium held in the very old university town of Durham, about a 3.5 hours (very pleasant) train ride up the English countryside from London. This was the brainchild of Prof. Michael Bohlander, the German jurist and international criminal court justice who leads up the Law department at Durham University. The colloquium’s title—“Alien Conversations: An Interdisciplinary Colloquiumon the State of Research and Policy Implications Concerning UAP and other Formsof Alien Encounter”—was a reference to a very famous (some might say infamous) event, held many years ago at MIT, organized by none other than MIT professor David Pritchard (who joined us via Zoom in Durham) along with the esteemed John E. Mack (someone whose esteem might be considered suspect by some). That event was more of a full-blown conference: “Alien Discussions” was the title given, described as a “secret MIT conference” by at least one reviewer in 1993. Mack’s and Pritchard’s event, focused on the abduction phenomenon (wave?) that saw its heyday in the 1990s, yielded a proceedings volume, and examining the table of contents one finds a roster of some of the most famous names in ufology and alien abduction studies—the very state of the art at the time.
Bohlander’s event, no less controversial even if rather less
grand in form and numbers in attendance, found several interesting talks, with mine
being perhaps the least of these, given its informational focus: I was invited
to speak about the journal Limina and the academic society (the Society
for UAP Studies) I founded last year (my talk, which, due to an unfortunate
technical glitch, failed to be recorded, nevertheless seemed to be rather well-received I
have to say). Of especial note was the talk by one of SETI’s more intrepid of
researchers—a leader in the area of post-detection SETI studies. I am speaking
of Prof. John Elliot of St. Andrews (just up the road in Scotland), who, way back
in the late 90’s, pioneered the study of the question of what sort of meaningful
content might be contained in a verifiably anomalous SETI signal indicative
of intelligent life abroad. It’s all well and good to find a signal, and for it
to pass the criteria set to establish it as of non-terrestrial technological
origin; but then what? Might it contain meaningful information? Enter
Prof. Elliot, whose expertise is in the area of computational linguistics (and
he’s quite a brilliant mind, to boot).
The Durham colloquium was simply too short to get the kind of
energetic intellectual exchange going that Alex Wendt managed to achieve at Ohio
State—but then again, it was a really hard sell for Durham to get this
on the docket, and then to have senior SETI personnel to be involved. The
tensions between SETI and the UAP crowd were somewhat in evidence, especially when
one prodded Elliott a bit. But you get a sense that, if we’re looking for
signals afar, and now technological signatures beyond mere electromagnetic blips,
why not “technosignatures” more generally? This is the push given
momentum by Loeb’s Galileo Project, which has no problem with allowing UAP—near
the Earth or on it—to figure into their search. After all, despite the strained
attempts to distance SETI from UAP, there’s absolutely no conceptual reason to
exclude UAP as candidates for an extraterrestrial signature right in our own
backyard—the unconscious fallacy of NIMBY-ism be damned.
Finally, I should at least outline my experiences at my very first
MUFON event as invited speaker. I thought I’d embarrass myself with my talk;
but as it turned out, I don’t think I did too badly. Perhaps I erred in terms of
the content, which might have been a bit too heavy. But I don’t think so: I think
the audience, all 10 attendees in person, and 9 or so online, appreciated what
I was trying to do, which was to find something of a middle-ground between
denialist debunkerism and credulous believerism, to move beyond this dead-end
discourse to something more open but more critical at the same time. Maybe I
wasn’t successful in achieving this; perhaps someone else cleverer than I
can do it right.
My talk was entitled “Transcendental Skepticism” and it’s
based on one of my very first blog posts. Now that I think of it, as I delivered
the talk on a beautiful late April evening in Orange County (it was Wednesday
the 19th), that marked almost the one-year anniversary of my blog.
Interesting coincidence. So I seem to have come full circle…
And so there you have it—my roster of scholarly ufological explorations
for the months of March and April. All in all, a rather rewarding (if tiring) intellectual
experience. I look forward to early May, when I fly down to Houston for the Archives
of the Impossible extravaganza, and later that same month when I embark on
my second ufological European adventure—first to Germany, then to Paris, then
to Portugal. I will attempt to chronicle this sojourn more faithfully in real-time
than I managed for my first set of trips. But as I have too much plated for me
from now and even through until then, and beyond (including preparing for Limina’s
first edition), I cannot exactly promise. I can hope.
Until then, pax vobiscum.
Thanks for this. Fascinating reading. Slightly envious that you get to do all this!
ReplyDeleteRe "how can we say that we are living up to our birthright as human beings—as homo sapiens? And how can one profess to love “science” in the widest possible sense of the word?"
ReplyDeleteFirstly, it's not a "birthright" it is an assumption or rather declaration to be homo sapiens, wise man.
Secondly, the declaration of humans being wise is really a lie and fantasy because at the core of homo sapiens is unwisdom (ie, madness) and so the human label of "wise" (ie, sapiens) is a complete collective self-delusion --- study the free scholarly essay “The 2 Married Pink Elephants In The Historical Room" ... https://www.rolf-hefti.com/covid-19-coronavirus.html
Once you understand that humans are "invisibly" insane (pink elephant people, see cited essay) you'll UNDERSTAND (well, perhaps) why they, especially their alleged experts, perpetually come up with myths and lies about everything ... including about themselves (their nature, their intelligence, their origins, etc).