of the matter of mind and matter: UFOs and 'psychical' effects

It was already a challenge to the research and study of the UAP phenomenon to produce “physical” evidence for it. This is surely the first task of any science: to show that a phenomenon not only (and simply) exists but is something that is amenable to investigation. And therein lies the very methodological, epistemological and even ontological crux of the matter (as it were): is there a ‘there’ there that is investigable?

The answer to this question is, upon reflection, no simple affair. Indeed, in answering it without deeper reflection, one is likely to be reliant upon certain presuppositions, and extending largely tacit paradigmatic assumptions, which have already determined the answer before it is given. Yet, we have to start somewhere, and make some assumptions, and see where that leads. When and where those assumptions break down—that’s when we start to notice them, and are forced to reconsider. It is not all a purely conceptual affair, after all. There is some there always there, and it might not be exactly amenable to the assumptions we make about it. But science works at least approximately well, to the extent that its presuppositions and working hypotheses are adequate to the phenomena it investigates—to the ‘there’. We always expect science to be capable of abandoning those working hypotheses, or of reevaluating its own presuppositions when they no longer seem to work out quite well, or well enough.

But there is a kind of nested hierarchy of these presuppositions, assumptions and working hypotheses we have to consider. Perhaps the most general are those that characterize the epistemological and ontological presuppositions of what Thomas Kuhn would have called a “paradigm” (or the philosopher of science Imre Lakatos a “research programme”—although Lakatos’ concept sought to improve upon Kuhn’s). These are very specific and very historically determined conceptual items that effectively regulate the various operating procedures, methods, and even the very conduct of the sciences in general. It is these kinds of presuppositions (about what knowledge is and how to get it, and about what there is in the world that can be known) that has the most immediate impact on the actual work of the sciences. It tells them generally where to look (the valid ontological field), and how to look at it in order to make discoveries or to solve problems (the acceptable norms of coming to know things).

Very early in the development of science—it was called at the time, wonderfully, the “New Science”, contrasting itself with the “old” worn “sciences” determined by an ancient paradigm rooted in Aristotelian philosophy—its basic guiding assumptions and general presuppositions began to be worked out. It all centered around, ironically enough, the nature of the human being involved in the investigation of the world it inhabits. It was almost inevitable: as the neatly self-enclosed Aristotelian universe, displayed in the Ptolemaic geocentric astronomical system, was found to be for various reasons deeply flawed, resting on a number of questionable presuppositions of its own (as that, for example, one could divine the “essence” of things by pure observation without direct engagement or testing), Descartes takes a step back and asks: if all I knew of the world, passed on to me by tradition, learned in school, and then repeated in taking up that tradition for further study and research—if all this was rooted in some system of knowledge that has not actually systematically inquired into, or even cared to account for, the fallibility of human knowing itself, is there anything I could know which was, in fact, reliably certain? What, after all, does human knowledge require for it to be at least possible to know anything absolutely, and securely (even if it not be attainable actually)? That is, Descartes had realized that the old science of the Schoolmen (as the theologically-centered intellectual authorities were called, given their origins in medieval scholasticism) had not yet attained to a self-aware, self-critical knowledge of method.

By asking this profoundly reflexive question—by calling into question the very possibility of any secure knowledge—Descartes did something monumental, and, in this gesture, brought the “modern” world into being. It forced a more honest reassessment of what it takes to know something, and to know with (at least the possibility of) certainty. His answer, of course, was rather deceptively simple (though dubious on its own terms, as all truly original works are), arrived at by means of a radical deconstruction of all human knowledge—by means, that is, of a radical skepticism of a kind not even the UFO debunkers are likely to entertain. If I can be wrong, Descartes reasons in the opening pages of his diamond work Meditations on First Philosophy, in what I might come to believe about something so basic as my own sense-perceptions (objects in the distance appear tiny, then magically grow as they approach me—yet are they really growing?), and if, when falling sound asleep, I come to accept the world of my dreams as the only world there is (can I thereafter really make a principled distinction between the “real” v. the “dream” world—or am I only capable of noting their relative differences?), then we must accept that it is possible that there is nothing about which I can be absolutely certain. Indeed: it is possible, for all I know, to be wrong about everything since for, all I know, my entire being could be nothing but the product of some “evil genius” (he says) who manipulates my very belief in things to suit some unknown purpose. If I can be fooled while dreaming, well perhaps I am always beings fooled even while awake. We are, after all, finite and profoundly limited creatures wholly dependent on other things for our existence. That dependence might mean we simply can trust nothing about what it is we think we know: we might be slaves to another more powerful but malevolently deceptive power. How deep should our despair be? Is there nowhere to land on firm ground?

At this point of extreme doubt and uncertainty, Descartes comes to a realization that, in truth, had already been arrived at centuries before in the deeply reflective Confessions of St. Augustine, a realization beautifully and concisely stated by the 20th century philosopher Wittgenstein: doubt—especially radical doubt—requires certainty. In other words, I must already be in order to be deceived. Try as they might, the “Evil Genius” cannot “cause me to be nothing, so long as I think that I am something”. That is: whenever I think, I exist. The Genius, if they exist, is trapped by their own deceptive plan for me: in deceiving me, they necessitate my existence! Otherwise, there would and could be no deception: nothing to deceive. This, according to Descartes, finally, is the necessary ground of all human knowledge, and it is an absolutely certain ground in the sense that even its doubt reasserts it as a presupposition supporting that doubt. Doubt has to come to an end somewhere; it cannot extend indefinitely.

In this way, Descartes returns knowledge to its origins in the act of thinking which we must necessarily employ as we try to know anything. If knowledge is to be certain, everything known must be linked to this certain ground of knowledge in reflective thought. The “I think, I am” must be at the root of it all. And if everything can actually be linked to it, then, by a certain chain of logical-conceptual links from this certainty to all subsequent knowledge flowing from it, the whole will be just as certain as its originating ground. Descartes comes to think that this is possible, and the entire Meditations are an attempt to demonstrate this in detail. What we are concerned with, however, is not his argument to that effect; rather, what we are concerned with is what Descartes contributed to the most general aspects of the nascent scientific paradigm that flourished in the decades and centuries following Descartes’ philosophical reflections on human knowledge. It has to do with the general distinction between “mind” and “matter”.

Descartes could not be certain about anything except the most basic thing: that as he thinks (and surely it is self-evidently true that he thinks!), he is certain that he exists—not, crucially, what he is that exists, or, more troublingly, that anything else besides this exists. It’s rather lonely in the beginning; but then again, I guess that’s just how it goes when you are the creator of something very new (“Let us make man in our image” was perhaps the cry of a lonely deity). This has a curious implication: what we call “matter” (or, to use the preferred term of the day: “body”) has an existence wholly suspect to the doubting “mind” which is now positioned in opposition to it. And what is born in this gesture is the fraught distinction between “mind” and “body”/“matter”. Following this philosophical method Descartes here institutes, we must arrive at something about this externality which can be known with certainty, starting only from the position of a doubting mind that knows only itself with absolute assurance. And here Descartes engages in a bit of creative thinking: let’s closely examine how non-mind stuff (“matter”) behaves when it undergoes all sorts of changes that we can imagine (or conceive) it undergoing. Things can lose their qualities, their shapes, smells, colors ... even the sounds they make might change under the right circumstances—all these identifying characteristics can undergo sometimes very radical change. And yet, something remains through it all. What is this something? Descartes hits upon it: the one thing that, if a thing lost it, would annihilate it altogether, making it into nothing, is its dimensionality. That is: “extension” (as he calls it). If a thing not be extended, it is nothing. Gone. Out of existence—at least as an external thing with which I can interact and about which I can think anything at all. Yet, when we reflect on thinking itself: can it, too, be considered “extended”? No, says Descartes: thought in itself has no such determination, because it can have neither length, breadth, height, nor either weight or “shape”. None of these characteristics apply to it (not literally, in any case), yet it most certainly exists by virtue of this whole exercise. It follows, Descartes concludes, that, whatever else they may be (and surely there is much more to say about them both), “thought” and “extension” constitute different “substances”—different basic kinds of thing that are separate but nonetheless equally real.

The consequences are profound, of course. With this distinction it becomes clear in what sense we might have not just a science of the natural world—considered in terms of “extended” stuff, or matter—but an exact science. If matter is essentially “extended” in terms of its most elementary dimensionality (length, breadth, etc.), and other quantities such as weight or shape (which may be tracked by means of matter’s more primitive structural dimensions), then it is absolutely clear how mathematics can be used to very exactly represent this reality. If something is extended, it can be mathematically represented. Since all matter is extended, and doesn’t exist without it, all material realities can be exactly represented and therefore studied mathematically. What about “thought”? What about the most essential feature of a human being—their “mind”? Well, the logic here is fairly simple: mind is not extended (indeed, mind and matter are oppositional), and therefore not amenable to exacting description in terms of mathematically representable quantities like dimension, weight, etc. Of course, as Descartes himself was aware, “thought” is in a sense describable in terms that may have a mathematical representation: for example, duration or persistence in time. Surely it makes sense to understand “thought” in these terms, since it makes sense to say that it happens within a certain amount of time, and time can be given a mathematical representation. The problem from Descartes’ perspective, however, would seem to be monumental: how can we non-arbitrarily relate the one (the duration of thought) to the other (the extension of matter or body apart from all thought)? The physical world of matter (of material bodies), we can now say, is representable with both duration and dimension, but “mind” with only one of the two. Mind is independent of matter, and matter of mind. It would only be possible to unite the two in a consistent framework of mathematical description by their interaction—but can they even interact? Can a non-extended something “interact” with that with is extended and has dimension? Problems seem to be mounting quickly here for Descartes peculiar answer to the problem of human knowledge.

It would only take a few decades (from the 1640s to the 1680s) to at least philosophically resolve these apparent problems in Descartes philosophical system (Spinoza’s solution was to argue that mind and matter are not separate “substances” but two aspects of the many possible for a single undivided and infinite “substance”), but by that time is was too late. The mind/matter distinction (and ensuing mind/body problem) was already locked in. Science was “exact” and about what could be “measured”: matter was in, mind was out. Mind—well, that was just nothing the New Science had much of anything to say about. Spirits, souls, angels, demons, fairy dust—all the same dubious “stuff”. If it can’t be stuff (extended, or thinking.), it can’t be at all. And if it’s not matter, then, well, it can only be “mind”—for what else is there other than the two, as Descartes had (putatively, of course) shown? Angels, demons, faeries, … well, it’s all just thought in the mind. To repeat: there are only two realities: thought, and external matter. Anything that exists will be in one or the other category. And the will not overlap in nature, only by joined by association (a mind associated to a body).

This is where we are still pretty much in our thinking to this day—in our conventional thinking, that is. We are very much committed to this tenuous Cartesianism, and it is well-entrenched in the traditional paradigm of science. It is reflected in both sides of the UFO controversy that has existed since the dawn of modern UFO studies. It is a fundamentalism that unites the seemingly opposed sides, despite their bickering and mutual antagonisms. The believers take the UFO to be an “objective” reality; the skeptics want to stuff it back into the minds of the believers (it’s all hoax, misperception, misinterpretation: human, all-too-human foibles of the mind). By insisting on the “objective” reality of the phenomenon, believers and UFO proponents accept the very same basic framework which the skeptics then employ to refute them. They both operate with the same naïve (and unexamined) Cartesianism.

The problem with this realization, however, is that, despite its subtlety, it does not have the virtue of being stated against an accepted, competing alternative to the Cartesian framework. While we can, from a purely abstract and logical point of view, attack the dispute as misguided Cartesianism, the burden is on this new skeptic—who recognizes and criticizes the common philosophical ground shared between UFO proponent/believer and UFO skeptic alike—to supply a concrete alternative with respect to which disputing the Cartesian standpoint makes sense. If the mind/matter split has become so well-engrained in science (and even to an extent in common-sense thinking), then the burden of proof has to be on the critic of this mindset. What is the simple, clear and practicable alternative?

It surely can be done—I have suggested it was done by Spinoza soon after Descartes himself expounded his system in the 1630s and 1640s; the problem was also taken up in various ways by Kant, then Hegel, then Husserl and the phenomenological tradition (and we’ll have occasion to return to these philosophers in future posts)—but what has not yet been achieved is a radically new and generally accepted scientific methodology derived from any of the alternatives which can also claim undeniable successes. You see, for all of its faults, flaws, stupidities, mistakes, and intellectual naivety, the general Cartesian paradigm of a mathematically representable world of measurable quantities evolving in time, objectively accessible to all by means of repeatable experiments and interactions capable of being intersubjectively experienced and encountered by anyone, anywhere has been quite successful within its restrictive epistemological parameters, with its most conspicuous failures cropping up of late in the so-called mind sciences. This relative success, however, does not in itself conclusively demonstrate the truth of the paradigm, of course—let’s not suddenly forget the underdetermination thesis, which applies not just to theories, but also to the paradigms within which theories are conceived. Surely there are different ways of conceiving of the world that are responsive to the same facts—with the important caveat being that the paradigm changes the manner in which facts are themselves conceived, so that relating them across paradigms is not and never a simple or straightforward affair. (One thinker who pointed this out—yet another unread but significant one—was Owen Barfield. His concept of “figuration” is crucial here.) But surely it can with significant effort be done: after all, Aristotle’s science was not entirely wrong relative to subsequent paradigms; one might even say that it remains to be seen the extent to which Aristotle was wrong or right, as our knowledge changes from epoch to epoch. Let’s not forget that the history of science teaches us, among other things, that we are getting some things right, others wrong, so that we are always in a process of approximation, testing, experimentation.

What remains to be seen, then, is an alternative paradigm to the naively Cartesian one with which we’ve been operating in science for centuries, one that also yields both method and model for prediction, control, experiment, hypothesis-testing, and so on, as well as a litany of successes to enshrine it in the pantheon of accepted scientific wisdom. In a Spinozan world, for example, we might ask: does anything crucial change in terms of scientific methodology? Is the terrain of phenomena altered such that quite new things are describable, and hence theorizable—and in new ways? What does this mean for mathematics, or for systems of representation more generally? Is our current system of mathematical representation and modeling tied inherently to Cartesian assumptions, or are they easily freed of them? Many have written on this question, and scholars far, far more gifted than I have weighed in. Yet, somehow, through all of it, the dominant paradigm plods along. (We should note that there are indeed many who are actively working to overturn this paradigm, and offering scientifically viable, complex and nuanced alternatives to it. For example, there is a new work that, boldly, calls itself a treatise in twenty-first century natural philosophy”: Emergence In Context by Bishop, Silberstein (one of my own philosophical mentors), and Pexton. It is up to future historians to say whether we here in the twenty-first century are living during another time of great scientific change and upheaval. We may very well be. George Steiners conference and subsequent edited volume on the question as to whether science is nearing its limits is, perhaps, a telling historical clue.)

Finally, we come around to how this is relevant for a science of UFOs. I think it is most clearly and immediately relevant whenever we must tackle the very difficult challenge of “high strangeness” sometimes associated with UFO encounters. It is what Vallée tries to deal with (poorly in my view), as he separates the UFO phenomenon into its “physical” and “psychological” or “psychical” aspects (that is: matter v. mind). What we are suggesting is, of course, that this very dichotomy itself may be dubious, especially if it is just the naïve Cartesianism all over again. And if this dichotomy ends up coloring or determining the nature of our subsequent theorizing of the phenomenon, then that theorization will suffer as a result: it will be only as secure as the presuppositions upon which it rests. In other words, dubious philosophical assumptions in, dubious philosophical conclusions out.

So, again: is there a there there when it comes to the UFO phenomenon? It is surely something there when we have multi-channel corroboration of the phenomenon. It is not just a thing seen; it is something present for both human and non-human (which is to say human-made, instrument-based) observers alike. But we surely can’t from here just jump to our sophisticated position of critique, and take the position that, abstractly, it is neither “out there” nor “in here”—that it is neither matter nor mind. Maybe that is ultimately true, but at this level of analysis it would be a mistake to bring in what could only be a metaphysical alternative which does not yet offer a methodological or descriptive one. Precisely and exactly this is the outstanding challenge of a future UFO science.

Perhaps we should approach the problem differently. Perhaps we might begin with the very naïve assumption: there is an object “out there” which I, “in here”, witness as an independent observer. Does this assumption break down in our investigation of the phenomenon? It possibly does. And let us let the experience and engagement with the phenomenon itself guide us here…

What do we mean?

Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that the so-called “psychical” effects on percipients of UFOs establishes a direct relation between the subject and the object. Let us for example assume that there is a reliable and strong correlation between the states of consciousness of the subjects/percipients and the UFOs they perceive or otherwise come into contact with. Let us also assume that no known energy or other influence can account for such a correlation (although ufology is filled with such attempts to physically locate a supposed cause for the psychological/psychical effects). We may then say that we have an anomaly: a strong correlation between subject/object that has no likely “physical” explanation. Under these circumstances, we would be forced to posit a new kind of matter/mind relation that evades a framework of explanation in terms of mediate or intermediate physical causes. This would, then, constitute a clear breakdown of the naïve Cartesian presuppositions of all conventional science. Or, in the very least, it would imply the existence of new heretofore unknown physical causes (energies, forms of matter) capable of generating this correlation. (Let us not forget that we are always able to extend any given paradigm by introducing auxiliary assumptions: in this case, we would have to hypothesize a new form of matter or energy to account for the directness of the relation about which we are here speculating. Either that, or, as we are suggesting, we ditch the attempt to posit causal relations between Cartesian pairs.)

Is this hypothetical “direct relation”, however, not already a problem which science faces today quite apart from the UFO quagmire? We ourselves house this problem! Let us not forget that, as a direct consequence of the naïve Cartesian presuppositions of science, human subjectivity itself, “consciousness”, that most basic and elementary aspect of our life, could not properly be comprehended by science except in terms of its “physical” characteristics—despite the obvious fact that when I see red or feel pain, it itself is no such physical thing to be found anywhere in or on the material body. When I look at my own brain, even—the supposed seat of my whole consciousness—I look upon it as if upon anything else in the world: it is still a mere object among others. Examining it more closely, when I see or touch or hear, there is nothing colored, touching (!) or audible there. Somehow, it happens in two ways: as an “experience” and as an associated (we may say correlated) physical event somewhere throughout my material body. Right here, with “consciousness” are we dealing with a direct mind-matter relation. It is well-understood that this is a problem (the so-called “hard problem” of accounting for mind in a purely materially conceived world), and that some revision to at least the brain or “cognitive” sciences is called for if consciousness is to be adequately accounted for. Or, I should say more carefully: that this is an outstanding debate, with no widely accepted solution available. It may even constitute a “crisis” in the relevant sciences, if we take consciousness as a kind of (rather ironic) scientific anomaly. What would be unique with the UFO case, when looking at a primary mind-matter anomaly, would be that it is between consciousness and a (presumably) material object external to it. The “body” is not exactly “external” to “us”; rather, body and mind or consciousness plausibly form some kind of unity (albeit of a philosophically-metaphysically contested sort). With the hypothetical case of a direct mind-matter relation between human being (their consciousness, and possibly including their physical body itself, as some cases show immobilization, burning, etc.) and UFO, we’d have an even more profoundly anomalous possibility.

Now, of course, the immediate and justifiable reaction to this hypothetical case is that there must be some kind of physical explanation for this mind-matter relation. The thought here would be that, naturally, we’d find some radiation or other energy being emitted by the UFO, which would be the direct cause of the change in state of the consciousness of the UFO’s percipient. However, there may in fact be deeper structure to the correlations between object and subject that we cannot overlook (and there are some experimental and other research movements in this direction at the University of Cadiz in Spain, under the thoughtful direction of Prof. De la Torre).

For example, it is possible, to begin with, that no energy or other physical influence is detectable—at least in some cases—even though a mind-matter relation seems to nonetheless exist between subject and object. But, let’s suppose there is some UFO energy emissions that can be correlated with changes in a subject’s state of consciousness. If there is such an energy-based cause for changes in consciousness of the subjects, we might expect those changes to be random. But they needn’t be. We might ask: what is the change in consciousness itself “about”—that is, does the actual content of the consciousness feature in the correlation itself? Is there a consistent and coherent pattern of thought that is produced under similar UFO encounter scenarios? Maybe there is a general “feeling” associated with the UFO encounter; but maybe there is something much more specific going on. A certain feeling would be one thing (and we’d expect there to be great variations in this subjective affect across different subjects). But if there is something more specific going on, then this suggests something much more anomalous: that the consciousness of the subjects is very specifically and precisely being manipulated intentionally, or otherwise affected by the perceived object. This, then, would approach the level of directness we already and always experience when we do, feel or think anything: I want to move my hand up, and, behold, it happens. I might want to say that mind is “causing” the matter of the body to react and respond to it; Descartes seemed to want to resolve this phenomenon in that way, but he made the mistake of trying to resolve it on the side of a series of purely physical causes—except for the initiating cause of the thought or desire itself. But we end up with inconsistencies and paradoxes if we were to do this. (We get an intimation of Spinoza here: don’t split the phenomenon into two metaphysically distinct parts, the one having to “influence” causally the other; rather begin with understanding that the “mind” stands in an immanent rather than a transcendent relation to “matter”: the one is already within the other, and vice versa. Both are instead aspects of the same unified reality: “matter” is mind under this aspect; “mind” is matter under that aspect.)

Now this exercise is meant to show where and how naïve Cartesian presuppositions begin to fall apart as we try and put them to use in explaining certain phenomena. This is how science proceeds: it models with an existing toolkit of concepts, and in effect tests them against the behavior of things. There are always going to be gaps, places where a concept doesn’t really fit closely; but then there are ruptures, where the phenomena are simply recalcitrant, showing us they just don’t care for our presuppositions. Witness the struggles of a Kepler or a Planck, laboring for years with one set of assumptions, only to eventually strike upon a few simple (but radically unconventional) concepts to better fit with what the data were doing (Kepler’s ellipsoids for planetary motion; Planck’s “quantum of action” for the energy states of so-called “blackbody” thermodynamic systems). With the UFO, we should see it as being also caught up in the existing problems with a science of consciousness—a rather “conventional” problem (the irony quite well intended by that statement). But it might be far worse, of course, for the problem of “high strangeness” extends beyond the matter-mind relation we have so far considered.

Matter-matter relations would seem to be unproblematic—until you begin to reflect more deeply even there. What is gravity? It is a kind of energy or force, right? But energy is mediated by force-carrying particles—at least we’d like to believe that, after our fairly successful reductions of the energy of matter given off as radiation (that’s just stuff coming from the particles of matter, hitting and bouncing off other stuff), or the energy represented as electromagnetic radiation (that’s just photons—particles—of light bouncing around). Force is carried by something. So, too, we would like to think, of gravity. But what’s the particle? The “graviton”! Well, maybe. The problem is that we have two ways of “reducing” the phenomena of energy, matter and so on: the field and the particle concepts. Physics tries to marry them up, but it leads to a number of inconsistencies, most pronouncedly in “quantum field theory”. So, matter-matter relations are ok—up to a point. But then, not really.

And then there’s mind-mind relations …the most anomalous and “strange” of the strangeness in the UFO phenomenon, and certainly something that most will want to most definitely argue is not a there at all. Let’s talk about that for a moment, as we draw these once again absurdly long reflections to a close (of course, as Borges reminds us, endings are really just arbitrary abandonments, for the turn of the mind is never-ending).

Such would seem to only be a problem of so-called “paranormal” research. It is certainly one problem for it: telepathy for example would seem to involve a direct mind-mind relation. But in certain reported UFO close-encounters, thoughts are seemingly directly “transmitted” from one mind to another. We have a very intriguing case of this with the Ariel School incident we have already mentioned in a previous post (mostly imagery was allegedly “transmitted” or at least perceived mentally by the children who, again allegedly, witnessed “beings” moving about a landed UFO in the back of their rural schoolyard one morning in 1994). But notice the severity of the metaphysical and methodological problem that this and other similarly “paranormal” phenomena face: it is entirely a “mind” phenomenon (“mind-mind”, in our scheme)—something already a disputed or problematic category in science (to say nothing of the science of consciousness, to the extent it exists at all)! This, and exactly this, is why all such phenomena remain not only controversial but a veritable ticket from serious science to dismissed pseudoscience or quackery. By its very nature it eludes scientific confirmation and testing precisely because it is wholly confined to the mind-mind domain, thus inaccessible to the rigorously objectifying methods of the sciences (which, let’s be clear, attempt to objectify the subjective in some fashion). When it comes to consciousness itself all there are are correlations between “brain states” and “mental states”—a framework, again, very much contested and doubted by those cognizant of the metaphysical naivety it belies. With mind-mind relations, what is there to objectify? In mind-matter relations, at least one half of the relation is susceptible to objectification, just because a correlation between the one and the reported/experienced states of the other can be established empirically and therefore theorized as such (a correlation). When the correlation is itself between two events which only may be correlated with the “matter” (the brains) of each of the subjects independently of the other—there is no “direct measure” as it were of the mind’s contents except by subjective reports of those contents)—science is completely at a loss. Except, again, for the subjective reports themselves: “I heard in my mind alone so and so saying x, y and z” or “I saw these images given to me by x” and so on.

This is all not to disparage, of course, the actuality or veridicality of these reported experiences (that is another matter entirely, one we should address in future posts). It is simply to highlight the epistemic hurdles that must be overcome in order to even allow such phenomena to be admitted as really existing, such that a scientific account is called for—not to dismiss them, but to actually posit hypotheses in order to account for them: how and by what means are they possible? Although those might turn out to be the wrong questions to ask: as paradigms change, so do the phenomena and the questions that can be asked (with old ones falling away as meaningless or pointless or fruitless). Indeed, as the paradigm changes, this set of relations characterized in terms of “mind” and “matter” will likely fall away to something else entirely. But we can’t just say that and provide an abstract argument recognizing the metaphysical difficulties or flaws inherent in this way of thinking. Rather—and this is my dogma—any alternative must be derived by means of an immanent or internal critique of existing concepts, and be motivated by specific failures of the existing paradigm itself. It cannot be entirely an external critique that gets us there—unless that external critique is done more from methodological or even pragmatic than from exclusively metaphysical premises. This, finally, is why it’s useful to pursue the problem of matter-mind or mind-matter relations as they occur in the UFO problem; it is a way of pushing the existing paradigm beyond itself, so that it fails on its own terms—where “matter” is as challenged as “mind”.

The matter-mind anomalies, then, must be established with the statistical sciences we have available to us, so that we can at least posit a law of the phenomenon of matter-mind interactions that would then require an explanation which could potentially lead to hypotheses outside the standard repertoire of conventional science, but where it would be clear that this anomaly is certainly no worse than the one already encountered in our primary experience with mind and matter which we call “consciousness”. Only then could we countenance the more pronounced anomalies alleged by paranormal researchers, which find resonance with the high strangeness of some UFO encounters...



Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Rising Sun In The UFO Firmament: Reflections on the Sol Foundation’s Inaugural Symposium. Part One of Two.

Zenith: Final Reflections on the Sol Foundation’s Inaugural Symposium. Part Two of Two.

moving beyond the "moving beyond materialism" of Josh Cutchin